VOEGELIN -- RESEARCH NEWS

======================================================================
Volume III, No. 5                                         October 1997
======================================================================

In this issue:

        1.  _VOEGELIN -- A Voice of the Cold War Era...?  A COMMENT
            on a Eugene Webb review_, by Maben W. Poirier.
        2.  _The language of political diagnosis:  Voegelin's portrayal
            of social decline_, Geoffrey L Price.
        3.  _Bibliographic Update No. 7_.


  Note that in line with the policy set for submissions to VOEGELIN--
  RESEARCH NEWS, the editors also have submitted their pieces to an
  anonymous referee for assessment.


                           ================== 
 
AUTHOR'S NOTE:  Unfortunately, because this is an electronic piece, I  
have not been able to place diacritical characters over the appropriate  
letters in non-English words.  Please bear with this inconvenience.  

                                                             MWP 

_A COMMENT on a Eugene Webb review_.  


              VOEGELIN -- A Voice of the Cold War Era...? 
 
Reviewing Michael Franz's work _Eric Voegelin and the Politics of Spir- 
itual Revolt:  The Roots of Modern Ideology_, in Volume III no. 1 of  
this newsletter, Professor Eugene Webb invites us to revisit a number of 
themes that are central to Voegelin's thinking.  In this short piece, I  
would like to focus attention on two of the themes which Webb mentions,  
and to argue that in each case we may and indeed must take a stance dif- 
ferent from that which he advocates, if we are not to relegate Voegelin 
to the status of a barely relevant oddity from a former age. 

In the introduction to his review, Webb affirms that "...Voegelin [is] a 
voice of the Cold War era."  He proceeds to discuss at some length his  
grounds for this assertion, namely, the problems he finds associated  
with Voegelin's faulty understanding of gnosticism.  These introductory  
statements are recalled at the end of the review, where Webb questions  
the appropriateness of Voegelin's polemical style _in the world in which 
we live_.  He specifically queries the value of "...Voegelin's tendency  
to characterize thinkers he disapproved of as 'ideologists' and 'spiri- 
tually diseased.'"  Echoing Franz, Webb tells us that this was a ten- 
dency which often led Voegelin to shun what would have been more desir- 
able:  a sustained refutation of the thought of these thinkers.  This,  
Webb informs us, was because Voegelin "...viewed their error as delib- 
erate rather than as a serious attempt to understand...," ...which, by  
contrast, is what Professor Webb presumes that in most instances it was. 
 
At a later point in his review, Webb also wonders whether Voegelin was  
correct when he assigned "...moral culpability for unsound theoriz- 
ing...".  For his part, Webb certainly acknowledges that "ideas have  
consequences, and [we are] responsible for the consequences,...".  How- 
ever, he also makes clear that in his judgement, the era of the Cold  
War, when it may have been appropriate to assign culpability for flawed  
ideas, is over.  It belongs to the past.  A new age has dawned and--in
Webb's estimate--a different, and presumably less polemical, approach is 
now demanded. 
 
Now, this reading of Voegelin's approach to the thought of others gives  
rise to an interesting question:  Is what Webb points out as a feature  
of Voegelin's work, and considers inappropriate, truly a function of the 
times in which Voegelin wrote?  Or, is there something else involved  
here, something of moment, which Webb has incorrectly identified as a  
matter of period and of style?  The question is indeed crucial:  on the  
first alternative, there would be little left to Voegelin's scholarship, 
other than the concerns of a dated intellectual from a bygone and out- 
moded era.  
 
Perhaps the best way for us to elucidate the point in the space allotted 
us is to recall the central theme of another Plato scholar of the cen- 
tury, namely, Michael Polanyi, the Anglo-Hungarian physical chemist and  
philosopher of science. 
 
Amongst philosophers of science and epistemologists, Polanyi is remem- 
bered for his claim that knowing the truth (as best one can every know  
the truth) is not the product of the implementation of what many main  
stream philosopher of science view as methodologically correct proce- 
dures.  Nor is it, as many of us are brought up to believe, the result  
of "disinterested" rational discourse amongst intelligent participants  
in debate, as goodwilled as some or all of these participants may be.   
Knowing the truth, Polanyi contends, is the consequence of reasoning  
that is profoundly "interested" and biased.  Indeed, at the deepest or  
essential level, it is a function of _who one is_, Polanyi tells us, and 
_who one is_, is the result of one's having appropriated, and one's  
continuing to make his or her's, a particular "habit of being," if I may 
be permitted to borrow a phrase from the American short-story writer  
Flannery O'Connor.  In short, coming to the knowledge of the truth about 
a particular matter depends not upon our capacity to manipulate, in some 
_un_committed fashion, explicit concepts and ideas, but upon our having, 
over time, allowed ourselves to become so familiar and so intimate with  
the subject-matter referred to and identified by these concepts and  
ideas, that we might say of it, and of us, that _it has become us and we 
it_.  It resides so deeply within us that we find it impossible, or  
almost impossible, to say where it stops and we begin.  It is part and  
parcel of our _maniere d'etre_, ...no doubt a serious and yet rewarding  
case of _deformation professionnelle_.(1)  Viewed from a slightly dif- 
ferent perspective, we might say that knowing the truth about a subject
is a consequence of our having permitted this subject's ordinary and  
more arcane features to _dwell in us_, such that we can say of ourselves 
that we know more (because we know at the level of habit and corporally) 
about the issues involved than we can speak or make explicit.  It is  
upon this deep-seated awareness, _that has become us_, that we, as indi- 
viduals, draw when we make the truth of something transparent, and thus  
available to our fellow human beings to see and know explicitly.  Evi- 
dently, it is also important to recognize here that no _maniere d'etre_  
is absolutely adequate, in the sense of not being susceptible of im- 
provement.  But, of course, some _manieres d'etre_ are better than  
others.  It is all a matter of judgement and degree.   
 
By contrast to the person whose "habit of being" is, in some way,  
schooled, the person who speaks from a recognizably deficient, and per- 
haps even obviously defective experiential repository of awareness in a  
defined area of scholarship or practice, is, according to Polanyi, more  
or less prevented from knowing the truth in that area, because he or she 
is more or less crippled in his or her _maniere d'etre_.  The point here 
is that the limitations involved in one's failure to recognize truth are 
not strictly intellectual and cerebral.  They are personal and experi- 
ential, in the sense that they are the consequence of a less than rich,  
and sometimes impoverished, "habit of being."  Fortunately, in most
instance, this crippling is not willed, and so, we adjust to it.  We
tolerate it.  No, we do more than tolerate it.  We enter into debate with
and even challenge these deficiencies of being, in the expectation that
because they are not willed, there is hope for redress.  After all, the
challenging of unintended deficiencies is fundamentally what a good
education is about.  But what if this is not the case?  What if the
deficiencies are more willed than unwilled, more intentional than unin-
tentional, more deliberate than involuntary?  What then?  As we know
well, there are situations where this is the case amongst intellectuals. 
In such situations, we cannot proceed as though the deficiencies were
unintentional, intellectually honest, and hence susceptible of remedy by
convincing argumentation and other conventional means.  They are not; and
we simply have to recognize this.  These deficiencies are _willed_
partial visions representing themselves as desirable and more complete
visions, ...half-truths, partial truths and ideologies, pure and simple,
masquerading as genuine truths, because fundamentally their authors
really do know them to be inadequate, while they try to hide it from the
rest of us.  Of course, the point here is that we are not dealing with
the deficiencies of a person who is open to the experiential.  Rather, we
are dealing with the deficiencies of one who has deliberately closed
himself off to life in the interest of pursuing an illusory certitude,
while, at the same time, knowing, to the extent to which he or she is
alive at all, that that sort of certitude is not possible.  Still more to
the point, we have to identify those who "reason" this way for who they
are, _because we judge them to be unworthy of serious exploration in the
area in which they claim expertise, since their ignorance is knowingly
cultivated and willed_. 
 
The point of interest for us here is that the truth of this theory of
knowing does not vary with whether an age is more or less polarized  
and ideological, more or less influenced by the ethos of the "Cold War." 
It is a general theory of knowledge that Polanyi advanced, ...a theory  
that has continuing relevance, and is true irrespective of the times and 
the customs of an era.  And so the implementation of this theory of  
knowledge does not vary either.  Knowing the true and the real is always 
deeply rooted in the personal, and entails what is personal in both its  
emergence and its failure to emerge.  It is true that in an environment  
that is attentive to the need to foster experientially based knowledge,  
the task of reaching out to others who are genuinely deliberative is  
usually easier, because the roots of unknowing are less deep.  But, even 
under these circumstances, the climate of the times does not forestall,  
in an absolute sense, the possibility that we may encounter a "will- 
fully" closed spirit, since ideological thinking is not a respecter of  
eras.  Nor is it only political in character as the expression "Cold War 
era" seems to imply.  Ideological and experientially "blinkered" visions 
come in a variety of forms and challenges us at different levels.  We  
are increasingly cognizant of this in this era of dogmatic relativism  
following hard upon the heels of scientism.   
 
Now, if I understand Voegelin correctly, he is in broad agreement with  
Polanyi's epistemology.  This is not to say that he based his theorizing 
on Polanyi's thought.  I see no explicit evidence that he did.  In fact, 
I am rather inclined to believe that he may not have read Polanyi, since 
I recall no mention of Polanyi's name in any of Voegelin's writings.   
Yet, the emphasis that Voegelin placed on experiential openness as the  
basis of knowledge goes a long way towards demonstrating the filiation  
between the two.  And so, like the Plato scholar Polanyi, the Plato  
scholar Voegelin knew that concern for the truth is more than a product  
of disinterested cerebration, and the entertainment of error likewise.   
Both are deeply rooted in the personal, and as a consequence, _in a very 
profound sense, we are the authors of our vision and of our blindness_.  
Hence, Voegelin's use of words like "ideologist" and "spiritually dis- 
eased" to describe the writings of leading contemporary thinkers is not  
a matter of style related to era.  It is a way of drawing attention to  
the _ultimately willed character and personal origins of someone's fail- 
ure to know_.  When employing these terms to describe the thought of  
someone, Voegelin is recognizing, and, by implication, asking us to rec- 
ognize, that the error that is present in the thought of the other is  
not innocent or unintentional.  It is error that is rooted in a defi- 
ciency at the level of the other's "habit of being," or general "open- 
ness to experience," and it can only be corrected by a reform willfully  
undertaken by that individual and designed to amend his or her "habit of 
being."  In other words, reform takes place through conversion (_peria- 
goge_) from a closed to an experientially open soul and not simply  
through cerebration.  No disinterested rational discourse will suffice  
when it is a matter of overcoming _willful_ ignorance.  Willful igno- 
rance, like the pursuit of knowledge and the truth, is chosen and is  
personal, and so the terms "ideology," "ideologist," and "spiritually  
diseased" are appropriate when describing the production and identity of 
certain individuals. 
 
And so, faulting Voegelin for not treating error, on what was at times a 
monumental scale, as nothing more than a product of disinterested rati- 
ocination gone awry or well-intentioned miscalculation, misses the whole 
point of Voegelin's argument.  Such error is precisely not a consequence 
of well-intentioned miscalculation by people who always want the best  
for the rest of us, and it can never be that, for one who argues that  
scientific truth cannot be pursued from a strictly instrumentalist per- 
spective.  The fact is that Voegelin viewed many of his "opponents" as  
either knowingly and positively evil individuals, or boring dilettantes  
because they failed to appreciate that the root of truth and error is  
not to be found in abstract reasoning, but in a person's "habit of be- 
ing."  And generally the dilettantes, the majority to be sure, were all  
too true to type to be really interesting from an intellectual per- 
spective.  Many were more interesting as expressions of particular mod- 
ern, and sometimes not so modern, pathologies rooted in their _maniere  
d'etre_ as well as that of the age, than as expressions of well-inten- 
tioned individuals whose instrumental reasoning power had deserted them  
momentarily.   
 
It was primarily for these reasons that Voegelin viewed ignorance as  
culpable.  When one spends a good part of one's life knowingly or half  
knowingly distorting one's "habit of being," whatever error results from 
this misguidedness is culpable error to one degree or another.  Indeed,  
it has to be culpable error, ...not in the sense that Professor Webb  
understands it, but in the sense that one is responsible for having led  
oneself into error.  The willful cultivation of crippling habits is not
without consequence, and one is responsible for the consequences as they 
play themselves out in oneself, as one is also responsible for the cul- 
tivation of habits that liberate.  Of course, it is also true that ideas 
have consequences, and that we may be responsible for their consequenc- 
es, in the sense that Professor Webb remarks.  But that is a very dif- 
ferent matter from the issue that was of concern to Voegelin when he  
spoke of ignorance as culpable.  For example, one might want to hold  
Lysenko responsible for the consequences of his ideas on two different  
levels; _one_, because of the terrible repercussions that they had on  
the study of genetics in the Soviet Union, as well as for the devasta- 
tion they caused Soviet agriculture, and the resultant starvation of  
untold numbers of people, and _two_, because the inadequacy of his ideas 
was a direct result of a personality flaw, which need not have existed,  
but which had to do with Lysenko's willful rejection of the true and the 
real, in the interest of maintaining a partial vision and an ideological 
outlook.  Untruth at this level is the result of more than just well- 
intentioned but poor calculation.  It is a consequence of a moral fail- 
ure of major proportions, and as there is no era when it will be possi- 
ble for us to say that finally we are exempt from such failings, there  
is no era when it will be inappropriate for us to identify them for what 
they are.            
 
In conclusion, I return to Professor Webb's views.  I maintain that he  
has seriously misread the significance of Voegelin's use of words like  
"ideology," "ideologist" and "spiritually diseased" when he reads sees  
these words as instances of poor manners, and if not poor manners, then  
poor style in an age when we are encouraged to think that our opponents  
are, first and foremost, honest with themselves and well-meaning.  This  
misreading leads Webb to characterize Voegelin as a dated cold-warrior:  
and that in turn unfortunately leads him to sidestep the central issue  
in all of this, which is the centrality to Voegelin's thought of his  
philosophical anthropology and his theory of consciousness. 
 
In short, I believe that if Professor Webb is serious in the points he  
makes, then he has obviously had a profound change of mind about who  
Voegelin was, and indeed about what human identity is, for what he re- 
commends is nothing less than the complete denaturing of both.  
 

M.W. Poirier, Concordia University, Loyola Campus, MONTREAL, Quebec    
      
 
                              -------------- 
 
                                   NOTES 
               
1  Polanyi relates knowing to being in the title of his article "Knowing 
and Being," which appeared in the journal _Mind_ in 1861, as well as in- 
directly in the many references he makes throughout his writings to the  
phenomenon of _indwelling_.  In addition, his principal collaborator,  
Marjorie Grene, who frequently knew what Polanyi meant as well as any- 
one, and is said to have helped Polanyi put his epistemological thinking 
in order, entitles her anthology of Polanyi articles _Knowing and Be- 
ing_:  _Essays by Michael Polanyi_ (1969).  But the most telling remark  
that Polanyi himself makes about the relationship of knowing to human  
being comes in the 1964 Preface to the Harper Torchbook edition of  
_Personal Knowledge_:  _Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy_, where he  
very explicitly states:  "All understanding is based on our dwelling in  
the particulars of that which we comprehend.  Such indwelling is a  
participation of ours in the existence of that which we comprehend; it  
is Heideggar's _being-in-the-world_."  In other words, all understanding 
is a function of indwelling, and indwelling is being-in-the-world or  
_maniere d'etre_.  And so, Polanyi's epistemology is very definitely  
more than just an epistemology.  It is also an ontology.   


          ====================================================


               _The language of political diagnosis:
              Voegelin's portrayal of social decline_

                          Geoffrey L Price


    In the context of the current debate about Voegelin's use of 
strongly polarized language, this note examines passages in his 
correspondence where equivalent points are put to him directly, and 
he defends his analysis. 

    In his article "The World of Homer" (_Review of Politics_ 15 
(1953): 491-523) Voegelin maintains that 

     "The Homeric poems are not concerned with causes and effects on 
     the level of pragmatic history but with the phenomenon of decline 
     itself. His Achaean society is disordered insofar as on 
     decisive occasions the conduct of its members is guided by 
     passion and desire rather than by reason and the common good.  
     The blinding through passion, the _ate_, is not the cause of 
     disorder; it is the disorder itself" (492).

Developing his argument, Voegelin examines the anger of Achilles in 
the _Iliad_, and the fruitless attempts by Phoenix his old educator 
to bring him to reason. Achilles' deep-seated wrath, penetrated only 
by the death of his friend Patroclus, profoundly disturbed the order 
of existence for those he lived and fought with (493-503). But that 
disturbance was only an episode in the greater context of a war that 
had been caused by the fatal attraction of Helen. Why had the quarrel 
not been resolved earlier?  To understand this, Voegelin studies the 
scenes with Paris and Helen, concluding that 

          "Homer uses these scenes quite deliberately for the purpose 
     of characterizing the disordered sentiments through the ranks of 
     the constitutional hierarchy.        
     ...
     Paris and Helen are the gap in the Trojan order through which 
     a dark force of destruction pours in, as Achilles was the gap in 
     the order of the Achaeans" (507).

     A copy of this article was sent by Voegelin to Mrs Elizabeth de 
Waal, then living in Tunbridge Wells, Kent, England.  She had 
followed Voegelin's work since the period in Vienna when both had 
been members of the study circle around Othmar Spann, and she had 
detailed knowledge of how narrowly Voegelin had escaped from Austria. 
In a letter of 23 July 1938 written to him at the hotel in Zurich 
which he had succeeded in reaching, she writes

          "Es ist buchstaeblich wahr, dass ich, seitdem ich Ihren 
     Brief bekam, allnaechtlich von dem schrecken Traume, den 
     Sie und Lissy durchgemacht haben muessen.  Gott sei dank haben 
     Sie noch einen Schutzengel gehabt. Ich zittere zu denken, was 
     sonst geschehen waere. Wenn nur jetzt auch Lissy gut 
     herauskommt. Ich teile Ihre Sorge um sie und hoffe Tag um Tag zu 
     hoeren, dass sie bei Ihnen ist."

        "It is absolutely true, that since I received your letter, I 
     have been up through the night over the terrible dream, of what 
     you and Lissy have been through. Thank God you still had one 
     guardian angel. I shudder to think what might have happened 
     otherwise. If only now Lissy can get through safely. I share 
     your concern for her, and every day I hope to hear that she 
     has reached you."

     During the war, Mrs de Waal describes the war situation within 
England, and the tension that isolation from the Netherlands was 
causing to her husband and his Dutch family. During and after the 
war, Voegelin sent her copies of work in progress: sections of the 
_History of Political Ideas_, and the articles "Plato's Egyptian 
Myth" (_Journal of Politics_ 9 (1947): 307-24) and "The Origins of 
Scientism" (_Social Research_ 15 (1948) 462-94).

    On receiving "The World of Homer," Mrs de Waal reacted critically 
to the style in which it was written. In her letter of 3 February 
1954, after enquiries concerning Voegelin's health in the aftermath 
of surgery, and news of the T.L.S. review of _The New Science of 
Politics_, she continued:  

        "When I say  I was immensely interested in your `World of 
     Homer,' that is to be taken quite literally. I confess I had 
     never thought much about the political and ethical significance 
     of the epics nor had my reading chanced on any of the 
     interpretations which, I infer from your article, are accepted 
     as to their place in the cycle of antique civilizations. I have 
     been given quite a lot to think, and to read about. Your 
     detailed interpretation is also very fascinating and throws new 
     light on many phases of thought and expressions. The only 
     quarrel I have with you is about the tone in which you write. 
     Why are you so contemptuous and derisive about Homer's heroes? 
     In all their human frailty, shortcomings and even moral 
     turpitude, they and their surroundings are surely clad in the 
     dignity of great poetry, and do not deserve to be spoken of like 
     a gang of bandits or the inmates of a thieves kitchen. You call 
     Achilles `a healthy _specimen_,' as if he were a dog or a head of 
     cattle; Priam `the royal gentleman,' as if he figured in a 
     musical comedy piece; Penelope's suitors are constantly referred 
     to as `rotters,' as if they were members of a gang of thugs. By 
     this contemptuous and if I may say so, inappropriate language - 
     of which I have only given a few instances that have stuck in my 
     mind, but which prevails throughout the essay - I feel that you 
     do less than justice to your theme, and you debase Homer to the 
     level of one of the less reputable popular newspapers. It is a 
     pity. - you are rather inclined to use this tone when you are 
     disputing a point with an author with whom you do not agree. I 
     have noticed it in the `Science of Politics,' and I think it 
     weakens the argument (apart from being unpleasant,) but you have 
     never applied it to your subject matter as you do here.

        Will you forgive me for saying this? I presume on our old 
     friendship for the liberty of making this criticism, and because 
     I would wish many readers for your most significant ideas, and I 
     wish these readers to enjoy them, without that feeling of 
     distaste and slight sickness aroused by the slangy expressions 
     in which they are presented. But then, perhaps Americans like 
     that sort of language; I'm afraid we don't over here."

     Voegelin replied quickly, writing from Baton Rouge, Louisiana on 
11 February 1954. He opened by acknowledging the force of the 
criticisms:

        "Thanks for [your] kind letter of February 3rd. I hasten to 
     answer it, in order to assuage all sorrows that I would take your 
     criticisms (or any criticisms which you ever have to offer) in 
     ill [_sic_]. Of course not; on the contrary, I am grateful for 
     it, especially when it concerns my style which I know all 
     too well leaves much to be desired.

          Hence I acknowledge the justice of your remarks with regard 
     to slangy expressions, especially since I am also aware of this 
     defect, and I am doing best in the revision in which I am engaged 
     at present to eliminate such sores if I can catch them. There 
     will be no `Healthy specimen' or `rotter' in the book-form of 
     the History."

In the event, when the article was incorporated into chapter 3 of 
_The World of the Polis_, Voegelin did not moderate his terms: 
Achilles remains a "healthy specimen" (p.85), and the suitors of 
Penelope are still described as "rotten" (p.99).  However, the 
real point of substance is that which is developed in the next 
paragraphs of his reply.

        "Not so sure am I about the justice of your remarks about the 
     `tone' of contempt with regard to Homeric heroes. While `rotter' 
     is slang and should not be used when speaking of the suitors, I 
     cannot be blind to the fact that for Homer they are `dogs.' 
     (Also the adjective is used which is difficult to render in 
     English. In the German translations it reads `huendische Freier' 
     and `huendische Weiber,' when Penelope speaks of the women of 
     her household who side with the `dogs'). Homer is very careful 
     to distinguish between the social rank of suitors when speaking 
     as a narrator (they are always the `noble suitors') and their 
     moral quality which appears when Odysseus or Penelope speak of 
     them, that is, the persons who have to `suffer' from the 
     discrepancy between social rank and moral stature. 
     That happens to be the problem of the social and political 
     crisis; and the hero is the `sufferer' who in the end restores 
     order by a mass slaughter of the `dogs'.

          The same difficulty arises with regard to Priam. You 
     complain that he is spoken of as if he were a farcical figure in 
     a musical comedy. I am not so sure that precisely this 
     impression was intended by Homer. If we trust the Greeks who 
     [sc. were] somewhat closer to the epics than we are, and perhaps 
     took them more seriously and not only as great poetry, we must 
     consider the attitude of Herodotus. (At least I must consider it 
     in the context of my `History'[sc. of Political Ideas]). 
     Herodotus does not believe that Helen was ever in Troy, but 
     that she was stranded in Egypt and there retained by the 
     Egyptians for return to her husband. His reason is the following: 
     It cannot be assumed as within the realm of possibility that any 
     government would let its city go to destruction for no other 
     reason than the one given by Homer: that the old king wants to 
     feast his eyes daily on the presumably attractive lady and does 
     not want to miss her. For a Greek with as large an intellectual 
     horizon as Herodotus, Priam was so farcical indeed that he was 
     implausible. He presumes that the Achaeans conducted the war 
     against Troy because they did not believe the assurances of the 
     Trojans that Helen really was not there at all.

          Furthermore, I have to take into account that Plato wants to 
     banish Homer from his _Politeia_ for precisely the reason which 
     you adduce in his favor in your letter: the great poetry of 
     Homer throws the golden veil of his magnificent verse around 
     persons and actions which are contemptible, and thereby may 
     induce acceptance of the standards of morality of the persons 
     thus glorified.

          I can understand quite well that you [sc. do] not like to 
     see Homeric heroes in an unheroic light. (You are not the only 
     critic who has expressed dismay at their treatment). But I hope 
     you will see that the matter is not simple for, because I have 
     to consider the Homeric heroes in the light in which they were 
     seen by the Greeks -- not in the light in which they are seen by 
     contemporary readers. It will require a very judicious weighing 
     of the `tone' if I want, on the one hand, not to fall into 
     slang, and, on the other hand, not to falsify the intentions of 
     Homer and the sense in which his work was understood by such men 
     as Herodotus or Plato.

          And now I only beg you not to take these explanations as 
     dogmatic on my part. I have simply stated reasons -- which are 
     open to be invalidated by counter-reasons. And I hope very much 
     to hear from you in the matter.

          I enclose an article on the Oxford Political Philosophers 
     [sc. _Philosophical Quarterly_ 3 (1953): 97-114)]. You will 
     perhaps find it also contemptuous in tone. But you will find in 
     it also some explanations why sometimes a tone should be 
     contemptuous, and not be genteel under pretext of innocuous 
     `disagreement with other authors'. I just recall a phrase from 
     the author of the _Screwtape Letters_: It is advisable to keep 
     an open mind with regard to technical inventions, kitchen-
     appliances and the like; to keep an open mind with regard to the 
     Ten Commandments is `moral imbecility'. There seems to be a 
     point where unequivocal expression of contempt is in 
     order; a point at which the pretext of amiable conversation about 
     intellectual matters with `colleagues' would be collaboration in 
     crime.

        Well, let that be enough for today. I only wanted to answer 
     that particular question raised by you.

             With all good wishes from both of us,

                Yours most sincerely

                    [E.V.]"

    In conclusion, may I remind readers of Voegelin that this use 
and defence of Homer's moral understanding of the sources of 
social and political decline is found not only in his reading of the 
Trojan wars themselves, but that it forms the whole basis of the 
treatment of order in Greek society in volumes 2 and 3 of _Order and 
History_.  His judgements on the limitations of the accounts of Greek 
history in Herodotus and Thucydides, and the Homeric underpinning 
of his own account, are presented in chapters 1, 3 and 12 of volume 
2.


                 ==================================


                    _Bibliographic Update no. 7_

              Essays from the 1994 Manchester Conference
           Essays on Voegelin in the 1995 Lonergan Workshop
                 Reviews and articles by Gregor Sebba
           Portuguese edition of History of Political Ideas
                  Recent books, articles and reviews


Clifford, Craig. _The Tenure of Phil Wisdom: Dialogues_. Lanham, 
    Maryland: University Press of America, 1995.

Cooper, Barry. "Eric Voegelin's Analysis of the Deformation of 
    Consciousness in Voltaire." _Lumen_ 15 (1996): 37-55.

Gebhardt, Juergen. "The Vocation of the Scholar." In _International 
    and Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Eric Voegelin_, edited by 
    Stephen A. Mc Knight and Geoffrey L. Price, pp. 10-34. Columbia, 
    Missouri: University of Missouri Press, 1997.

Germino, Dante. "Voegelin's two portraits of Hooker and their 
    relation to the modern crisis." In _Richard Hooker and the 
    construction of Christian community_, edited by Arthur Stephen Mc 
    Grade, pp. 351-68. Tempe, Arizona: Mediaeval and Renaissance Texts 
    and Studies, 1997.

Harter, Nathan. "Eric Voegelin on the Authority to Lead." _Modern 
    Age_ 39 (1997): 21-27.

Hopkins, Jasper. "Interpretive Study [Includes detailed critique of 
    treatment of Nicholas of Cusa in Blumenberg, Hans. _Die 
    Legitimitaet der Neuzeit. 2nd edition. 3 vols. Frankfurt am Main: 
    Suhrkamp, 1973-76 / _The Legitimacy of the Modern Age_, 
    translated by Robert M. Wallace. Cambridge, Massachussets: MIT 
    Press, 1985." In _Nicholas of Cusa's Dialectical Mysticism. Text, 
    Translation and Interpretive Study of _De Visione Dei_, pp. 3-97. 
    Minneapolis, Minnesota: Arthur J. Banning Press, 1985. ISBN 0 
    938060 28 7.

Jackson, Nigel. "`The values we live by." Review of Eric Voegelin. 
    _New Science of Politics_." _News Weekly (Victoria)_ (1970): 10.

Kloczowski, Pawel. "Faust's Alma Mater." In _Cracow: The Dialogue of 
    Traditions_, pp. 21-33. Cracow: Znak, 1991.

Lawrence, Frederick G. "The Problem of Eric Voegelin: Mystic 
    Philosopher and Scientist." In _International and 
    Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Eric Voegelin_, edited by 
    Stephen A. Mc Knight and Geoffrey L. Price, pp. 35-58. Columbia, 
    Missouri: University of Missouri Press, 1997.

Leone, Carlos. "`Realismo espiritual, politica e transcendencia.' 
    Review of Eric Voegelin. _Estudos de Ideias Politicas_.
    _De Erasmo a Nietzsche_. Lisbon: Atica, 1996." _Expresso 
    (Lisbon)_ (10 May 1997): (Livros).

Levy, David J. "Europe, Truth and History: Husserl and Voegelin on 
    the Identity of Europe." In _International and Interdisciplinary 
    Perspectives on Eric Voegelin_, edited by Stephen A. Mc Knight and 
    Geoffrey L. Price, pp. 59-83. Columbia, Missouri: University of 
    Missouri Press, 1997.

Maier, Hans. _Politische Religionen. Die totalitaeren Regime und das 
    Christentum_. Freiburg: Alber, 1995.

---, ed. _Totalitarismus und politische Religionen. Konzepte des 
    Diktaturvergleichs_. Paderborn: Schoeningh, 1996.

Martins, Herminio. "Hegel, Texas: Issues in the Philosophy and 
    Sociology of Technology." In _Knowledge and Passion: Essays in 
    Honour of John Rex_, edited by Herminio Martins, pp. 226-49. 
    London: J.B. Tauris, 1993.

McKnight, Stephen A. "Eric Voegelin, the Renaissance _Prisca 
    Theologia_ Tradition, and Changing Perspectives on the Gnostic 
    Features of Modernity." In _International and Interdisciplinary 
    Perspectives on Eric Voegelin_, edited by Stephen A. Mc Knight 
    and Geoffrey L. Price, pp. 135-58. Columbia, Missouri: University 
    of Missouri Press, 1997.

Morelli, Mark D. "Affinities of Lonergan and Voegelin." _Lonergan 
    Workshop_ 12: _In Tune with the Divine Ground: Cultural and Social 
    Conditions for Political Order_ (1996): 179-198.

Morrissey, Michael P. "Voegelin, Religious Experience and 
    Immortality." _Lonergan Workshop_ 12: _In Tune with the Divine 
    Ground: Cultural and Social Conditions for Political Order_. 
    (1996): 199-226.

O'Carroll, Noreen. "A Biographical Sketch of Eric Voegelin." 
    _Milltown Studies_ 38 (1996): 19-33.

O'Grady, Desmond. "The Symbolization of Reality." _Milltown Studies_
    27 (1991): 105-135.

Price, Geoffrey L. "Science, Idealism and Higher Education in 
    England: Arnold, Green and Haldane." _Studies in Higher Education_ 
    11 (1986): 5-16.

---. "Critical History after Augustine and Orosius: Voegelin's Return 
    to Plato." In _International and Interdisciplinary Perspectives on 
    Eric Voegelin_, edited by Stephen A. Mc Knight and Geoffrey L. 
    Price, pp. 84-116. Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri 
    Press, 1997a.

---. "Recent International Scholarship on Voegelin and Voegelinian 
    Themes: A Brief Topical Bibliography." In _International and 
    Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Eric Voegelin_, edited by 
    Stephen A. Mc Knight and Geoffrey L. Price, pp. 189-214. 
    Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri Press, 1997b.

Purcell, Brendan. "Universal Viewpoint and Universal Humanity: 
    Attunement or Discord in the Philosophies of Voegelin and 
    Lonergan?" _Lonergan Workshop_ 12: _In Tune with the Divine 
    Ground: Cultural and Social Conditions for Political Order_. 
    (1996): 227-249.

Ranieri, John. "Question and Imagination: Eric Voegelin's Approach." 
    _Lonergan Workshop_ 11 (1995): 105-143.

Richert, Scott P. "Review of Ted Mc Allister. _Revolt against 
    Modernity: Leo Strauss_, Eric Voegelin and the 
    Search for a Post - Liberal Order_. University of 
    Kansas Press, 1995." _Review of Metaphysics_ 50 (1997): 675-676.

Sandoz, Ellis. "The Crisis of Civil Consciousness: Nihilism and 
    Political Science as Resistance." _Political Science Reviewer_ 25 
    (1996): 22-42.

---. "Introduction." In Eric Voegelin. _Science, Politics and 
    Gnosticism_, pp. vii-xx. Washington, D.C.: Regnery Publishing, 
    1997.

Sebba, Gregor. "`Eric Voegelin: From Enlighenment to Universal 
    Humanity.' Review of Eric Voegelin. _The Ecumenic Age_. Order   
    and History. Vol. 4. 1974." In _The Collected Essays of Gregor 
    Sebba_, edited by Helen Sebba, Anibal A. Bueno and Hendrikus 
    Boers, pp. 189-96. Baton Rouge, Louisiana: Louisiana State 
    University Press, 1991a.

---. "Greek Tragedy and the Search for Truth." In _The Collected 
    Essays of Gregor Sebba_, edited by Helen Sebba, Anibal A. Bueno 
    and Hendrikus Boers, pp. 139-62. Baton Rouge, Louisiana: 
    Louisiana State University Press, 1991b.

---. "History, Modernity and Gnosticism." In _The Collected Essays of 
    Gregor Sebba_, edited by Helen Sebba, Anibal A. Bueno and 
    Hendrikus Boers, pp. 51-111. Baton Rouge, Louisiana: Louisiana 
    State University Press, 1991c.

---. "Order and Disorders of the Soul: Eric Voegelin's Philosophy of 
    History." In _The Collected Essays of Gregor Sebba_, edited by 
    Helen Sebba, Anibal A. Bueno and Hendrikus Boers, pp. 163-88. 
    Baton Rouge, Louisiana: Louisiana State University Press, 1991d.

---. "Prelude and Variations on the Theme of Eric Voegelin." In _The 
    Collected Essays of Gregor Sebba_, edited by Helen Sebba, Anibal 
    A. Bueno and Hendrikus Boers, pp. 197-226. Baton Rouge, Louisiana: 
    Louisiana State University Press, 1991e.

---. "The Work of Art as Cosmion." In _The Collected Essays of Gregor 
    Sebba_, edited by Helen Sebba, Anibal A. Bueno and Hendrikus 
    Boers, pp. 287-304. Baton Rouge, Louisiana: Louisiana State 
    University Press, 1991f.

Voegelin, Eric. _Science, Politics and Gnosticism_. 1968. Washington 
    D.C.: Regnery Publishing, 1997.

Vondung, Klaus. "Die Apokalypse des Nationalsozialismus." In _Der 
    Nationalsozialismus als politische Religion_, edited by Michael 
    Ley and Julius H. Schoeps, pp. 33-52. Bodenheim: Philo, 1997a.

---. "Eric Voegelin, the Crisis of Western Civilization, and the 
    Apocalypse." In _International and Interdisciplinary Perspectives 
    on Eric Voegelin_, edited by Stephen A. Mc Knight and Geoffrey L. 
    Price, pp. 117-34. Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri 
    Press, 1997b.

Walsh, David. "Foundational Reality in Voegelin and Lonergan." 
    _Horizons (Milltown Institute, Dublin)} 8 (1974): 89-96.

Walsh, David J. _The Growth of the Liberal Soul_. Columbia, Missouri: 
    University of Missouri Press, 1997.

Webb, Eugene. "Eric Voegelin at the End of an Era: Differentiations 
    of Consciousness and the Search for the Universal." In 
    _International and Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Eric 
    Voegelin_, edited by Stephen A. Mc Knight and Geoffrey L. Price, 
    pp. 159-88. Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri Press, 
    1997.


======================================================================
---------   Archive Address:  vax2.concordia.ca/~vorenews   ----------
======================================================================
Dr. M.W. Poirier                  | Dr. Geoffrey L. Price
Dept. of Political Science        | Dept. of Religions and Theology
Concordia University              | University of Manchester
Loyola Campus                     | MANCHESTER M13 9PL
7141 Sherbrooke Street W.         | United Kingdom
MONTREAL, Quebec                  |
H4B 1R6                           |
E-Mail: poirmw@Vax2.Concordia.Ca  | E-Mail: g.price@manchester.ac.uk
======================================================================